top of page
Writer's pictureDaryana Gubareva

Mill’s Harm Principle

Introduction

“I can do what I want, and if it doesn’t harm you, you shouldn’t bother me” is, in simple

words, the Harm Principle. John Stuart Mill was an English legal philosopher who

introduced the Harm Principle and stood for the utilitarian concept. Mill also advocated for liberalism, the foundation of which is the concept that regulation and convictions

should be rightfully justified. Individuals cannot be prosecuted without reasonable

grounds; they are permitted personal liberty against the state, law, and any public

authority. The Harm Principle proposed by Mill in his book On Liberty promotes this

concept and will provide the majority of the ideas demonstrated in this article. This

concept is quite controversial and has been debated for many years; one of the

contentions is the contrast between public morality, private morality and how they

integrate into law.


BBC Radio 4 (2014)


Freedom of Action

"The only freedom which deserves the name, is that of pursuing our own good in our

own way, so long as we do not attempt to deprive others of theirs, or impede their efforts to obtain it." That is the foundation of the harm principles. Mill proposed that individuals should be permitted to live their life as they desire, partake in what they want, and act the way they want. He believed that the law does not have the right to impede this liberty unless the consequence of this liberty leads to harm to others. In addition, a lawful conviction of these "liberal" actions should be on reasonable grounds. Someone's actions contradicting societally set ethical behaviours do not constitute valid grounds for a conviction. This collective morality should not have a say in people's individual choices. In addition, he stated, "...the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant." Mill emphasised that the law, authority, and community do not have the authority to prevent someone's actions "for their sake." People have the right to make their own choices, and these choices should not be punished. He reiterated freedom and liberty as something that is pursuing your own decisions.


Freedom of Speech

Mill did not only advocate for personal liberty in actions but freedom of speech as well.

Mill believed that free speech is critical for world progression. Expressing oneself and

sharing opinions leads to development. While censorship only impedes it, in the case

that it does not destroy it. The individual shall decide their decisions and express them

at their own peril. Furthermore, Mill stated that if an outcome would cause offence, that

is not enough to constitute harm; hence the harm principle is upheld.


Octaviano, E. (2020)


Counter Arguments

The front-door privacy concept — ‘don’t bring that out on the street’. Mary Midgley

argued that if something is happening behind the eyes of the people it does not mean it

should be ignored. If people are given the discretion of liberty in their choices, when the

“doors” will open, unimaginable things could emerge. Notwithstanding, the view of Mary

Midgley, the Harm Principle revolves around individual liberty that does not cause harm

to others. Mill explains that liberty should not be abused, it should permit one to have

authority over themselves. Furthermore, Sir James Stephen insisted on the fact that harming oneself, is harming others - “there are acts of wickedness so gross and outrageous that they must be punished at any cost to the offender.” In simple terms, he states that the authority has the duty to protect the public morality. It is only appropriate that the law is used towards the benefit of the society by punishing those that go against common morality. To this Mill once again replied that the public do not have the authority to impose their opinions on individuals. A person should choose what they want or do not want.


Conclusion

The Mill’s Harm Principle is not entirely refined; thus, many questions about real-life

contentions arise. What about euthanasia? Does harming oneself fall within the harm

principle? How are foetuses regarded? All these questions are valid; however, they all

have the same moral argument as the harm principle. It is the debate on how much

morality should be integrated into law.

As Mill never addressed these questions himself, people have proposed solutions, for

example, considering the above scenarios as victimless crimes. This extension further

supports the idea of private actions, as all of those crimes do not include a victim. They

do not infringe on other people's rights.

Should the law be able to regulate personal liberty of choice and actions that do not

infringe on other people's rights? - A question that cannot be answered. There are

specific arguments for Mill's Harm Principle and particular against it; hence, it is unlikely

for a concession to be reached. Nonetheless, it can always be debated.




Work Cited

BBC Radio 4 (2014). The Harm Principle: How to live your life the way you want to.

YouTube video. Available at: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=R9IM3ZKNMCk&t=11s.

Courtland, S.D., Gaus, G. and Schmidtz, D. (1996). Liberalism. The Stanford

Encyclopedia of Philosophy, [online] (Spring 2022 Edition). Available at:

https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2022/entries/liberalism/.

Macleod, C. (2016). ‘John Stuart Mill’. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,

[online] (Summer 2020 Edition). Available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mill/.

Midgley, M. (2017). Can’t we make moral judgements? London Bloomsbury Academic.

Mill, J.S. (1859). On Liberty. S.L.: Arcturus Publishing Ltd.

Octaviano, E. (2020). Morality and Law Balance. pixabay.com. Available at:

https://pixabay.com/photos/legal-right-justice-law-of-nature-5293009/.

Comments


bottom of page